William of Ockham
also called WILLIAM OCKHAM, Ockham also spelled
OCCAM, byname VENERABILIS INCEPTOR
(Latin: Venerable Enterpriser), or DOCTOR
INVINCIBILIS (Invincible Doctor), (b. c.
1285, Ockham, Surrey?, Eng. d. 1347/49, Munich, Bavaria [now in Germany]),
Franciscan philosopher, theologian, and political writer, a late scholastic
thinker regarded as the founder of a form of nominalism the school of
thought that denies that universal concepts such as father have
any reality apart from the individual things signified by the universal or
general term.
Early life
Little is known of Ockhams childhood. It seems that he was still a
youngster when he entered the Franciscan order. At that time a central issue of
concern in the order and a main topic of debate in the church was the
interpretation of the rule of life composed by St. Francis of Assisi concerning
the strictness of the poverty that should be practiced within the order.
Ockhams early schooling in a Franciscan convent concentrated on the study
of logic; throughout his career, his interest in logic never waned, because he
regarded the science of terms as fundamental and indispensable for practicing all
the sciences of things, including God, the world, and ecclesiastical or civil
institutions; in all his disputes logic was destined to serve as his chief weapon
against adversaries.
After his early training, Ockham took the traditional course of theological
studies at the University of Oxford and apparently between 1317 and 1319 lectured
on the Sentences of Peter Lombard a 12th-century theologian whose
work was the official textbook of theology in the universities until the 16th
century. His lectures were also set down in written commentaries, of which the
commentary on Book I of the Sentences (a commentary known as
Ordinatio) was actually written by Ockham himself. His opinions aroused
strong opposition from members of the theological faculty of Oxford, however, and
he left the university without obtaining his masters degree in theology.
Ockham thus remained, academically speaking, an undergraduate know
as an inceptor (beginner) in Oxonian language or, to use a
Parisian equivalent, a baccalaureus formatus.
Ockham continued his academic career, apparently in English convents,
simultaneously studying points of logic in natural philosophy and participating
in theological debates. When he left his country for Avignon, Fr., in the autumn
of 1324 at the pope's request, he was acquainted with a university environment
shaken not only by disputes but also by the challenging of authority: that of the
bishops in doctrinal matters and that of the chancellor of the university, John
Lutterell, who was dismissed from his post in 1322 at the demand of the teaching
staff.
However abstract and impersonal the style of Ockhams writings may be,
they reveal at least two aspects of Ockhams intellectual and spiritual
attitude: he was a theologian-logician (theologicus logicus is
Luthers term). On the one hand, with his passion for logic he insisted on
evaluations that are severely rational, on distinctions between the necessary
and the incidental and differentiation between evidence and degrees of
probability – an insistence that places great trust in mans natural
reason and his human nature. On the other hand, as a theologian he referred to
the primary importance of the God of the creed whose omnipotence determines the
gratuitous salvation of men; Gods saving action consists of giving
without any obligation and is already profusely demonstrated in the creation of
nature. The medieval rule of economy, that "plurality should not be assumed
without necessity," has come to be known as
Ockhams razor; the
principle was used by Ockham to eliminate many entities that had been devised,
especially by the scholastic philosophers, to explain reality.
Treatise to John XXII
Ockham met John Lutterell again at Avignon; in a treatise addressed to Pope
John XXII, the former chancellor of Oxford denounced Ockham's teaching on the
Sentences, extracting from it 56 propositions that he showed to be in
serious error. Lutterell then became a member of a committee of six theologians
that produced two successive reports based on extracts from Ockham's commentary,
of which the second was more severely critical. Ockham, however, presented to
the pope another copy of the Ordinatio in which he had made some
corrections. It appeared that he would be condemned for his teaching, but the
condemnation never came.
At the convent where he resided in Avignon, Ockham met
Bonagratia of Bergamo, a doctor of civil and canon law
who was being persecuted for his opposition to John XXII
on the problem of Franciscan poverty. On Dec. 1, 1327,
the Franciscan general Michael of Cesena arrived in
Avignon and stayed at the same convent; he, too, had been
summoned by the pope in connection with the dispute over
the holding of property. They were at odds over the
theoretical problem of whether Christ and his Apostles
had owned the goods they used; that is, whether they had
renounced all ownership (both private and corporate), the
right of property and the right to the use of property.
Michael maintained that because Christ and his Apostles
had renounced all ownership and all rights to property,
the Franciscans were justified in attempting to do the
same thing.
The relations between John and Michael grew steadily
worse, to such an extent that, on May 26, 1328, Michael
fled from Avignon accompanied by Bonagratia and William.
Ockham, who was already a witness in an appeal secretly
drafted by Michael on April 13, publicly endorsed the
appeal in September at Pisa, where the three Franciscans
were staying under the protection of Emperor Louis IV the
Bavarian, who had been excommunicated in 1324 and
proclaimed by John XXII to have forfeited all rights to
the empire. They followed him to Munich in 1330, and
thereafter Ockham wrote fervently against the papacy in
defense of both the strict Franciscan notion of poverty
and the empire.
Instructed by his superior general in 1328 to study
three papal bulls on poverty, Ockham found that they
contained many errors that showed John XXII to be a
heretic who had forfeited his mandate by reason of his
heresy. His status of pseudo-pope was confirmed in
Ockhams view in 1330-31 by his sermons proposing that
the souls of the saved did not enjoy the vision of God
immediately after death but only after they were rejoined
with the body at the Last Judgment, an opinion that
contradicted tradition and was ultimately rejected.
Nevertheless, his principal dispute remained the question of poverty, which
he believed was so important for religious perfection that it required the
discipline of a theory: whoever chooses to live under the evangelical rule of
St. Francis follows in the footsteps of Christ who is God and therefore king of
the universe but who appeared as a poor man, renouncing the right of ownership,
submitting to the temporal power, and desiring to reign on this earth only
through the faith vested in him. This reign expresses itself in the form of a
church that is organized but has no infallible authority either on the
part of a pope or a council and is essentially a community of the faithful
that has lasted over the centuries and is sure to last for more, even though
temporarily reduced to a few, or even to one; everyone, regardless of status or
sex, has to defend in the church the faith that is common to all.
For Ockham the power of the pope is limited by the freedom of Christians that
is established by the gospel and the natural law. It is therefore legitimate and
in keeping with the gospel to side with the empire against the papacy or to
defend, as Ockham did in 1339, the right of the king of England to tax church
property. From 1330 to 1338, in the heat of this dispute, Ockham wrote 15 or 16
more or less political works; some of them were written in collaboration, but
Opus nonaginta dierum (Work of 90 Days), the most voluminous,
was written alone.
Excommunication
Excommunicated after his flight from Avignon, Ockham maintained the same
basic position after the death of John XXII in 1334, during the reign of
Benedict XII (1334-42), and after the election of Clement VI. In these final
years he found time to write two treatises on logic, which bear witness to the
leading role that he consistently assigned to that discipline, and he discussed
the submission procedures proposed to him by Pope Clement. Ockham was long
thought to have died at a convent in Munich in 1349 during the Black Death, but
he may actually have died there in 1347. (P.D.V.)
Bibliography
Arthur Stephen McGrade, The Political Thought of William of Ockham:
Personal and Institutional Principles (1974), focuses on Ockham as a
political theorist and activist.
Gordon Leff, William of Ockham: The Metamorphosis of Scholastic Discourse
(1975), examines his system of thought. Marilyn McCord Adams, William
Ockham, 2 vol. (1987), discusses in detail his thinking on a variety of
complex topics.